ঠিকানা

পল্লবি, ঢাকা।
ট্রাভার্স সিটি, মিশিগান।

কল করুন

+১৯২৯৩৪৬২২০০

মেইল করুন

brandbangalee@gmail.com

Your Social capital will make your social politics smoother to ensure social Justice-Nayan Bangalee

রাজনীতি
social politics smoother to ensure social Justice

In the most recent studies of social capital in political science, the author contends that the researchers have significantly deviated from the approach that was taken in the beginning, which portrayed social capital as being endogenous. Recent studies have recast social capital as a component of political culture, treating values as exogenous in the process because of this recasting. These two ways of thinking are founded on premises that are irreconcilable with one another and lead to consequences that are radically different.

Therefore, attempts to integrate the two strategies will not be fruitful since there will inevitably be logical flaws within each of them. In addition, the empirical studies of the exogenous social capital method have a number of flaws, including the fact that they make selective use of the data and utilize ad hoc techniques at pivotal points in their analysis. Therefore, we strongly encourage a shift toward seeing social capital as an endogenous phenomenon.

Social politics smoother to ensure social Justice develop industrial section

Why have East Asian countries that are only now beginning to industrialize done so well? What are the most plausible reasons for the persistent discrepancies that exist between northern and southern Italy? Have people in the United States lost faith in the ability of their federal government to do its job? Is it necessary for a functioning government to have citizens who are willing to participate?

social politics smoother to ensure social Justice
social politics smoother to ensure social Justice

These weighty issues continue to get a significant amount of attention. There have been many various hypotheses put out in an attempt to explain these occurrences; but, in the most recent years, those theories that are couched in terms of social capital, community norms, or values have garnered particular attention. In point of fact, these theories have struck a responsive chord and have gotten an unusual amount of attention from academics, social and political critics, and the more general policy community.

Consequently, Senator Bill Bradley said, "Today the delicate ecology of our social environment is as imperiled as that of our natural environment," in a speech that he delivered to the National Press Club on February 9, 1995. It seems that the network of voluntary groups in the United States is withering away, much like dead fish floating on the surface of a polluted river. [A variation on this theme is the even broader and more apocalyptic suggestion that post–Cold War global politics is being reconfigured around cultural groupings, so that future wars will occur between states and groups from different "civilizations," but such claims are beyond the scope of this review.] [A variation on this theme is the even broader and more apocalyptic suggestion that post–Cold War global politics is being reconfigured around cultural groupings.] These explanations have an influence that may be felt far beyond the academic world.

Our goal is to conduct a comprehensive analysis of the growing body of research that has provided support for these hypotheses. Our contention is that the usefulness of these studies is far lower than it may at first seem. In point of fact, they diverge from the theories of social capital that are more logical and take us back to the cultural explanations that were popular a few decades or so ago. After providing a brief summary of the arguments that have received significant attention as of late, we go on to provide our verdict.

THE CONCEPT OF SOCIAL CAPITAL


The concept of social capital was established most explicitly by the late James S. Coleman (1988, 1990) as part of his endeavor to build a comprehensive, coherent theory of social interactions. Coleman's work was carried out as part of his endeavour to develop a broad, coherent theory of social relations. He utilized this phrase in connection with the ideas of physical capital and human capital, and he made clear contrasts between the three types of capital. Physical capital, of course, refers to investments in tools, machinery, and other physical forms of productive equipment.

Human capital, on the other hand, refers to investments in the expertise and knowledge of persons and is considered a less tangible kind of investment (see e.g. Schultz 1961, Becker 1975). Because it originates from shifts in the relationships between individuals, social capital is much less tangible than it already is. These shifts make it easier for people to take action. Coleman proposed that it takes on three distinct guises:

social politics smoother to ensure social Justice
social politics smoother to ensure social Justice

responsibilities and expectations, the fulfillment of which is contingent on the veracity of the social setting, the capacity for the flow of information within the social structure, and rules that are supported by consequences. One characteristic that is shared by the majority of different types of social capital and that distinguishes it from other types of capital is its quality as a public good. The actor or actors who generate social capital typically only capture a small part of its benefits, which is a fact that leads to underinvestment in social capital. (Coleman 1988, page S119) [citing]

Coleman's work has been cited by more contemporary scholars who have emphasized the importance of trust and social networks as important components of social capital. Putnam accepts the following definition of "social capital": "By'social capital,' I mean aspects of social life — networks, norms, and trust — that allow individuals to act together more effectively to achieve common objectives" (1995c, pp. 664–65). In point of fact, Putnam is quick to point out that his definition of social capital is just "slightly" different from Coleman's. According to Fukuyama, social capital is "a capacity that comes from the predominance of trust in a society or particular portions of it."

In other words, trust is the foundation of social capital social politics smoother to ensure social Justice. It is possible for it to take form in the smallest and most fundamental social group, the family, as well as in the biggest of all groups, the country, as well as in all of the other groups that fall anywhere in between (1995, p. 26). Using de Tocqueville and Putnam as a foundation, Inglehart defines social capital as social politics smoother to ensure social Justice "a culture of trust and tolerance, in which enormous networks of voluntary connections grow." These ideas are echoed throughout his interpretation of social capital. (Inglehart 1997, p. 188)

THE RECENT DEBATE CONCERNING SOCIAL CAPITAL

Putnam makes the argument that social capital "improve[s] the efficiency of society by promoting coordinated activities" in what is possibly the most well-known study ever conducted on the subject (1993, p. 167). Putnam uses rotating credit associations as an example of the unprompted cooperation that results from the presence of social capital. These associations can be found in Japan and other countries, and their members regularly contribute to a fund, the entirety of which is then given to a single member on a rotating basis. Why shouldn't a participant leave out after he has gotten the pot since these revolving credit relationships obviously contradict the concept of collaborative action?

When faced with such a danger, we cannot fathom why anybody else would contribute in the first place. (1993, p. 168). According to Putnam (1993, page 169), the explanation may be found in the "underlying pool of social capital." These linkages simply would not be conceivable without high levels of trust. As a result, the fact that rotating credit associations are "frequently found in combination with cooperatives and other kinds of mutual help and solidarity" should not come as a surprise to anybody (Putnam 1993, p. 169).

social politics smoother to ensure social Justice
social politics smoother to ensure social Justice

Putnam comes to the more general but similar conclusion that the effectiveness of regional governments is dependent on patterns of social networks by drawing on his broader evaluation of institutional performance across all 20 regions of Italy. This conclusion is based on Putnam's evaluation of Italy's regions (civic associations). The absence of a "civic culture" in many areas of Italy for such a long period of time has consigned those areas to a life of abject poverty and inept governance.

In a more recent study, Putnam (1995a, b, c) uses the same general framework to lament the political consequences of the decline of social capital in the United States over the last two decades. This decline has gradually produced a society of "go-it-alone bowlers," who are isolated not only from each other but also from the broader currents of community political life. Putnam laments the political consequences of the decline of social capital in the United States over the last two decades.

An analogous line of reasoning is presented in Fukuyama's (1995) investigation of the part that trust plays in the operation of markets. Fukuyama comes to the conclusion that the most important factor in generating growth is social capital in the form of a trusting culture, or as he refers to it, "spontaneous sociability." Although factors such as technology, markets, and human capital all contribute to economic growth, Fukuyama believes that the most important factor in generating growth is social capital.

The similar idea can be found in Harrison's conclusion (1985, 1992, and 1997), which states that political and economic progress are dependent on values such as trust, ethical norms, and attitudes toward labor and taking risks. Inglehart provides a little twist on the theme by asserting that trust and participation in voluntary groups are "highly associated" with stable democracy and the transitions to democracy that occurred between the years 1990 and 1995. This is a small modification of the motif (1997, pp. 189–205). (The findings of Inglehart, on the other hand, are inconclusive; the majority of the bivariate relationships he describes are, at best, only sporadically significant when other variables are taken into account.)

These are some of the most significant arguments that have been made in recent times about the tremendous economic, social, and political effects of social capital. If you take them to mean nothing more than the assertion that social capital is significant and deserving of inquiry, then they are harmless and do not significantly alter Coleman's initial analysis. Recent research, on the other hand, suggests that social capital is a reflection of long-standing cultural norms that cannot be described in terms of rational principles.

In addition, these standards operate as the primary external elements that contribute to the generation of economic and governmental performance. As a result, according to Fukuyama, "social capital, which is practiced as a matter of a rational habit and has its origins in 'irrational' phenomena like religion and traditional ethics, would appear to be necessary to permit the proper functioning of rational modern economic and political institutions" (Social Capital: A Rational Habit With Its Roots in 'Irrational' Phenomena) (1995, p. 325). The primary shortcoming of these arguments is that they try to rebrand social capital as a cultural phenomena. This is the most significant weakness of these arguments.

CONCLUSIONS of social politics smoother to ensure social Justice

Political science's social capital debates have diverged. Most significantly, the original argument saw social capital as endogenous, but contemporary interpretations have reverted to the political-culture tradition, which sees values as external. We have argued that these two techniques have incompatible foundations and fundamentally distinct ramifications, making integration implausible. Thus, it is not unexpected that such attempts suffer from internal logical errors, particularly those regarding basic values' persistence. Recent empirical assessments of the exogenous–social capital method utilize chosen data and ad hoc processes at critical points, highlighting these conceptual issues. A less selective and more consistent data analysis eliminates the argument's proof.

As demonstrated, endogenizing social capital is more compatible with the original social-capital theory. The endogenous–social capital argument, unlike the political-culture argument, is cohesive and accounts for crucial occurrences. It has more tangible policy consequences for observed change.

Banfield's 1958 "Montegrano" research shows that endogenous–social capital is better than exogenous. Banfield's 1954–1955, one-village research inspired Harrison (1992, 1997), Fukuyama (1995), and Putnam (1993)'s civic virtue analysis in Italy. Banfield's research blamed the "virus of amoral familism" (Pizzorno 1971, p. 92) for Montegrano's backwardness. The outlook was poor since the norm was engrained.

Harrison noticed "significant change" at Chiaromonte in 1989 on a "pilgrimage."

Literacy was widespread. Half were grads. All households had TV. 60% had phones. 60% drove. Several agricultural cooperatives existed. Families average two children. A 1970s motorway halved Naples travel time (from six hours to three). People travel more and attend school elsewhere. Many Chiaromontese have worked in Northern Italy and other European nations and returned. (Harrison 1992, p.80)

Harrison says, “Chiaromonte is no longer Montegrano” after 35 years of change.

It's hard to argue that amoral familism caused mid-1950s Montegrano's backwardness while including Harrison's 1989 Chiaromonte. After all, Banfield portrayed amoral familism as a basic worldview, too deep-rooted for the pattern Harrison found. That reversal was rapid, taking less than a generation and a half.

However, focusing on Chiaromonte people' incentive systems explains the observed shift. Overpopulation, deforestation, and a dearth of agricultural land plagued southern Italy following World War II (Schachter 1965). In 1952, the Association for the Industrial Growth of the Italian South estimated that over 7 million people (42% of the southern population) resided in zones "without consistent prospects of development" (cited in Lopreato 1965, p. 299).

Agricultural villages were plagued by bankruptcy, poverty, bad health, and social marginalization. Lopreato (1965, p. 300) claimed that over two thirds of Italian agricultural workers were dissatisfied with "their real living situations" in a 1952 national survey. “Little work, irregular labor, little money, excessive prices, hunger, and other economic causes and other difficulties” caused this dissatisfaction. In such an atmosphere, Banfield's mid-1950s findings of low trust and strong present-orientedness make sense. (Whether this constitutes "amoral familism" is another matter.)

Southern Italy changed after 1950. The push and pull effects of economic progress in the north and abroad drove considerable emigration. Lopreato recorded 2,500,000 migrants between 1951 and 1963. (1965; see also Goldberg 1996). This amount represents a stunning 14% of the southern population of 17,433,500 in 1951 and much more of the (possibly) economically-active work force. From 2,689,000 to 1,661,000, male agricultural employees fell 40%.

Changes prompted political action. Most importantly, national political parties saw southern concerns as a major vote-getter (Lopreato 1965). Harrison's new road from Chiaromonte to Naples has fresh importance here. Lopreato cited evidence that national governments increasingly acknowledged a "southern issue" and made steps to remedy it. In the early 1960s, a statute encouraged the consolidation of little inheritance-generated land holdings into bigger, more viable economic entities (Lopreato 1965).

Thus, Banfield's amoral familism was a legitimate reaction to southern Italy's 1950s incentives. After Banfield's study, this was constantly highlighted (see e.g. Marselli 1963, Pizzorno 1971, Silverman 1968). Emigration and Rome's political interest shifted incentives. Harrison's "new" Chiaromonte, whose amoral familism was accidental.

শেয়ার করুনঃ

Share on facebook
Facebook
Share on twitter
Twitter
Share on linkedin
LinkedIn
Share on telegram
Telegram
Share on whatsapp
WhatsApp
Share on email
Email

শেয়ার করুনঃ

Share on facebook
Share on twitter
Share on linkedin
Share on telegram
Share on whatsapp
Share on email

সাম্প্রতিক প্রকাশনাসমূহ

আমাদের সাথে যোগাযোগ করতে ইচ্ছুক?